Tags:
John, I really like the vignette you use to open your paper, as well as it's simple but profound question, "Why do Chinese gods look like that?" It raises many interesting questions.
Not being a regional specialist, my own question with be methodological. You begin by affirming Gell's critique of Bourdieu’s sociological and Panofsky’s iconographic approaches to art. The former “never actually looks at the art object itself,” while the latter “treats art as a species of writing” and thus fails to consider the object itself. You then state that your purpose is to consider what we might learn by going a step further and considering the object itself.
Saying as much, I thought the paper might be an elaborate discussion of the material forms of the gods themselves, perhaps by drawing explicitly on materiality studies such as Miller's own work or even a volume like Thinking Through Things (Henare et al 2007).
Instead, what largely followed was an analysis of various "representations of gods" in different contexts in the attempt to add up the "parts of the puzzle from which the anthropologist attempts to construct a convincing picture of the whole of what he is writing about."
Given your agreement with Gell's critique, how does a focus on representation and thick description go beyond Bourdieu and Panofsky, and toward the object itself?
"Why do Chinese gods look like that?"
Read the works of Terese Tse Bartholomew on Manchurian Sino-Tibetan art and iconography.
Justin, that's an excellent question to which I have no ready answer. Lin Wei-ping led me to Gell and my buying The Object Reader (Fiona Candlin and Raiford Guins, 2009), which contains the Gell essay from which the remark was taken. I have also had a quick look at Daniel Miller's Material Cultures. But that is pretty much the extent of my current exposure to materiality studies. It would be very helpful, indeed, if those who know more than I do would join in with tips about how they might apply.
Any thoughts?
Justin Shaffner said:John, I really like the vignette you use to open your paper, as well as it's simple but profound question, "Why do Chinese gods look like that?" It raises many interesting questions.
Not being a regional specialist, my own question with be methodological. You begin by affirming Gell's critique of Bourdieu’s sociological and Panofsky’s iconographic approaches to art. The former “never actually looks at the art object itself,” while the latter “treats art as a species of writing” and thus fails to consider the object itself. You then state that your purpose is to consider what we might learn by going a step further and considering the object itself.
Saying as much, I thought the paper might be an elaborate discussion of the material forms of the gods themselves, perhaps by drawing explicitly on materiality studies such as Miller's own work or even a volume like Thinking Through Things (Henare et al 2007).
Instead, what largely followed was an analysis of various "representations of gods" in different contexts in the attempt to add up the "parts of the puzzle from which the anthropologist attempts to construct a convincing picture of the whole of what he is writing about."
Given your agreement with Gell's critique, how does a focus on representation and thick description go beyond Bourdieu and Panofsky, and toward the object itself?
John: Apologies for not commenting sooner, but your paper raises some important and interesting issues which I wanted to think about before offering a response.
As I don't know anything about Chinese religions, I unfortunately can't offer much of a contribution to your informative discussion of that particular material. But your more general argument is most welcome, against the widespread scholarly tendency to want to see straight through the materiality of images, to access a meaning behind or beyond them - a tendency which is, I think, motivated by a modernist epistemology (Ricoeur's 'hermeneutics of suspicion', if you like), that thinks it comes equipped with a kind of X-ray vision, able to fathom and figure out the real depths of sense behind surface appearances.
One could say, I guess, that, for the devotees of these images, there is also something behind or beyond them; namely, the divinities that 'have no shadows and leave no trace', except that their hither existence is, as you indicate, captured or contained within the images themselves. But this notion that such images are temporary repositories of an efficacy that is also 'out there', is clearly different to the concerns of the art collector - unless, I suppose, the efficacy invested in the image is its monetary value.
I was definitely persuaded by your argument that, whatever Chinese divinities may look like, they don't look like they do just because Chinese society happens to look like that (gods as bureaucrats, etc). I entirely agree that this kind of quasi-Durkheimian move - religion is a projection of the social order - is too simplistic.
I also very much see eye to eye with your proposal that we should treat with the material specificity - the 'tangible qualities' - of the images themselves. It is interesting to learn that these images, and the gods invested in them, are defined in terms of their efficacy (ling). It almost made me think that the Chinese had already understood Gell's Art & Agency long before he came to write it!
Up to a point, your general proposal does sound rather like Gell, who you quote in support, and similar sentiments are expressed in a paper on Buddhist icons by Bernard Faure (writing completely independently of Gell), that we should attempt to
'free ourselves from the obsession with meaning (symbolism, iconology in the Panofskian sense) and form (style) in order to retrieve the affect, effectivity, and function of the icon. We need to go beyond the traditional concerns about the genesis of particular works of art; influences; attempts to retrieve historical or aesthetic categories (the sublime, and so forth)'. (Faure 1998: 787)
But as Justin notes, the programme of your paper moves in a rather different direction to the that one Gell takes. You aim to leave behind meaning (or, at least, leave behind the meaning behind images) towards a focus on forms, and - if I've read the argument correctly - you suggest that different forms of divine representation express and enable different kinds of relations towards divinities.
The contrast seems to turn on the difference between iconic and aniconic images. (The former: images that aim at resemblance; such as Chinese gods looking like people; the latter: images that don't obviously aim at resembling anything, such as gods represented as spirit tablets, or the concealed objects that embody the deities in Japanese shrines.) I could be mistaken, but I took there to be an extra, overlapping contrast: between images that can be seen (as in Chinese temples) and those that cannot (as in Japanese shrines).
At any rate, iconic images express or enable more intimate, reciprocal relations between worshippers and divinities, while the relationships that aniconic (or invisible) images project or promote is more authoritarian.
I think that the scheme introduces great scope for comparative possibilities, which is clearly the excellent intention behind it. But I have some reservations. As I remarked in a previous post, it does generally seem to be the case that Japanese Shinto shrines are devoid of any obvious iconic imagery. At least, a Shinto priest said as much to me, that, in shrines (as opposed to Buddhist temples), one cannot 'see' the god. So, there may indeed be something rather interesting at work here, but I'm not certain that there is necessarily a connection between an-iconicity (and/or invisibility of imagery) and the expression of authority. Or, to put it another way, it's not clear to me that aniconic or otherwise invisible divinities constrain the possibility of intimate relations with them. Contemporary ethnographies of Japanese shrine-going show both that the range of relations people aim to establish with the gods (as well as the ways they go about doing so) are very diverse, and the relations so established can indeed be intimate and reciprocal (see, e.g., Nelson 1996: Reader & Tanabe 1998).
Of course, on the face of it - if you'll pardon the pun - it would seem to be intuitively easier to establish more personal and intimate relations with an anthropomorphic and visible divinity or its image, because all the more easy to see it, to address it, to touch it (as in the nade-botoke that Faure mentions, 'buddhas to stroke' - Buddhist statues that worshippers touch in order that merit or benefits might rub off on them). But equally, many hundreds of thousands of Japanese go to shrines at New Year, in order to re-connect, to reciprocate, with gods that are either deemed to inhabit trees, stones, or are otherwise nowhere to be seen.
One last point. It seems to me that you hit on a potentially significant distinction: that between gods that are anthropomorphic and those that aren't - certainly, ancient Roman writers seemed to think so, noting that before the influence of the Greeks, their indigenous gods were never represented as people, but did their divinities change when the way they represented them did? Gell, at any rate, thought that the gods are what they look like:
'Whatever the idol looks like, that, in context is what the god looks like, so all idols are equally realistic, because the idol-form is the visual form of the god made present in the idol.' (Gell 1998: 98)
But this, of course, doesn't answer your question!
Refs:
Faure, B. (1998). 'The Buddhist icon and the modern gaze.' Critical Inquiry 24:3:768-813.
Gell, A. (1998). Art & Agency.
Nelson, J.K. (1996). 'Freedom of expression: The very modern practice of visiting a Shinto shrine'. Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 23:1-2:117-153.
Reader, I. & G. Tanabe. (1998). Practically religious: Worldly benefits and the common religion of Japan.
John, the response to Thinking Through Things you quote from above is by Daniel Miller, not Haidy Geismar. Readers may also be interested in Martin Holbraad's reply to Miller, which they can read if they scroll down past the bottom of Miller's piece.
Miller's take on the arguments are quite reasonably designed to reassert the place of material culture studies, which Miller (perhaps optimistically) locates at 'the vanguard of anthropology' (Miller is of course Professor of Material Culture at UCL), in response to our query in TTT 'what would an artefact-oriented anthropology look like, if it were not about material culture?’ Of course, what we were querying was not the existence or value of material culture studies as a (sub-)discipline, but why it is that anthropologists persist in segregating objects from their meanings. We were not the first to do so, of course, as we acknowledge in the following passage from the Introduction:
'Understood as a realm of discourse, meaning and value’, Tim Ingold has observed, ‘culture is conceived to hover over the material world but not to permeate it’ (2000: 340). On this model, meanings attach to things, impose themselves on things, may even be inscribed or embodied in certain things, but are always presumed to be – in the first instance – distinct from the things themselves. Marilyn Strathern (1990) has attributed this view to the epistemological preoccupations of a modernist anthropology that takes as its task the elucidation of social and cultural ‘contexts’ - systems or frameworks used to make sense of social life (see also Pinney 2005). In this scheme, she notes, the primary task of anthropologists is to slot things into the social and historical systems (such as ‘society’ or ‘culture’) wherein their significance is produced. One effect of this procedure is that the system itself becomes the object of study, its artefacts reduced to mere illustration: “For if one sets up social context as the frame of reference in relation to which meanings are to be elucidated, […] then explicating that frame of reference obviates or renders the illustrations superfluous: they are become exemplars or reflections of meanings which are produced elsewhere. It was in this sense that social anthropology could proceed independently of the study of material culture” (1990: 38).'
If you are really interested, as the beginning of your paper suggests, in approaching things such as Chinese gods differently, you might also look at Michael Taussig's work, since he somewhere asks and discusses a very similar question (if the statues only 'represent' the gods, why do they need bodies at all?).
Welcome to
Open Anthropology Cooperative
© 2019 Created by Keith Hart.
Powered by